I. Introduction
Socrates had said at 61c and 63b-c that a philosopher should be willing to accept his or her death, without resentment and with good hope. His young Pythagorean friends, Simmias and Cebes, asked him to explain and argue for that claim. From 63e to 69e, Socrates argued that if one accepts that
(a) death is the separation of body from soul and of soul from body, and
(b) what the philosopher seeks is a kind of knowledge that is not apprehended by the five senses (and this kind of knowledge can be hindered or confused by one’s body and its effects),
then
only in death, if at all, will the philosopher attain the knowledge that he or she seeks (67a).1 This conclusion depended in part on the assumption (65a and 66a) that a person is his or her soul (and not the complex of soul and body). For if a person is taken to be the complex of soul and body, the person would not be him- or herself when soul and body separate, so the philosopher would not be around after his or her death.
II. 70a-72e: an argument about opposites
Cebes points out that the chance to pursue knowledge without hindrance from one’s body will only be available to the philosopher if in fact the soul continues to exist and function after it has become separated from the body. That is, if the soul were to dissolve after separating from body, it would not exist to pursue knowledge. If the soul were to continue to exist but in a weakened or diminished state, it would not be able to pursue knowledge, or perhaps would not be conscious.2
Socrates produces an argument that purports to show that what is living must come from what is dead. Thus a living creature would come from a dead one, by reincarnation. This seems to require (at least, Cebes seems to accept that it requires) that a soul persists after its separation from one body, so that it can then make a new body a living creature.
The
argument has a number of flaws. These flaws are, I suggest, deliberate
on Plato’s part, and probably intended as deliberate on the part of the
character Socrates. The flaws as well as the valid reasoning pose
questions for the reader to consider, and also reveal issues that those
who engage in philosophy in the manner of Socrates’ friends will miss.
More on this appears below, and will emerge throughout our study of the
dialogue.
A. Socrates first asks Cebes whether all things that come to be and
have opposites come to be from their opposites (70e). Note that here
Socrates is not speaking of all
things, and he’s not speaking of things that come to be
but do not have opposites, but only of things that come to be and have
opposites.
Socrates gives examples that are intended to illustrate this:3
From these examples, Cebes agrees that all things come to be from their
opposites.
One problem with this conclusion is that, as we’ve noted above,
Socrates was not originally talking about all things; he has
not shown that all things come to be. This is important because
Socrates is going to argue later that certain things, such as soul, do
not come to be.
Socrates also has not shown that all things that come to be come to be
from their opposites, or even that all things have opposites. (Cebes,
as a Pythagorean, might miss this, because he might think he knows how
opposites work, or might think that all things exemplify opposites in
some way.)
Another problem is that even if we consider only things that come to be
and that have opposites, Socrates has not shown that all of those
things come to be from their opposites. He has only shown that if we
talk of things becoming more
one way or another, we say they must have gotten more that way after
being less
that way; if we talk of things becoming less one way or
another, we say they must have gotten less that way after
being more
that way.
That is, if we say that something comes to be largER than it was, we
imply that at one time it was smallER than it is now. But if we say
that something came to be large, or that a large thing came to be, it
may or may not be true that the thing used to be small. Perhaps it was
always large (maybe more so or less so, but still large). Or perhaps it
did not exist before, and as soon as it came into being it was large.
B. Socrates now asks Cebes to identify the processes by which things
come to be opposite - for example, increase and decrease (or growing
and shrinking) for things coming to be larger or smaller. In the case
of the opposite of dying, there does not seem to be a conventional
name, and Socrates proposes that they “supply” or “provide” one (71e).
In other words, he is suggesting making up a name for a process that he
has deduced should go on; and Cebes agrees.
Perhaps that would make more sense if the deduction were more solid.
But in fact it rests on some unsupported and unwarranted assumptions.
We’ve already identified some of them in II.A. Another one is that
waking always comes to be from sleeping, and vice versa. We don’t know
that that is true, and in fact both now and in ancient Greece it was
thought not to be true: at a certain stage of development, babies in
the womb begin to undergo cycles of movement and rest. It’s widely
thought that they go through sleep periods and waking periods at this
point. Before that, they are not sufficiently developed to do this.
Thus either their entry into these cycles is first sleep or first
waking, and what preceded it was neither sleep nor wakefulness. (If you
think babies don’t sleep or wake until they are born, then you would
say that their first state is either wakefulness or sleep, and that for
this baby there was neither sleeping nor waking before it.) Similarly,
a person who dies in his or her sleep has a period of sleep that does
not end in waking; one who dies during a waking period does not then
enter a sleeping period.4
III.
Recollection (anamnesis), 73a-77e
A. Socrates’ friends accept the argument that being alive must come
from being dead, and Cebes notes that this argument fits well with
another account that Socrates sometimes mentions, namely the account of
learning as recollection. Several dialogues have the character of
Socrates say that learning during human embodied life is recollection.
The relationship between the thesis that learning is recollection and
the argument that the soul persists after separation from body is that
(according to Socrates’ arguments) the knowledge that one recollects
during bodily life was originally obtained when one’s soul was separate
from one’s body. Each time one’s soul is reincarnated into a body, it
forgets this knowledge, and if one wants to get in touch with this
knowledge while in a body, one has to recollect it by a certain kind of
learning process (76c).5
The English word
‘recollection’ is being used in your text to translate the Greek anamnesis. The
root of the word is mne-,
denoting memory or remembering (Mnemosune
is the goddess of memory; a mnemonic device is a technique for
remembering). Amne-
adds the negative a-,
so words in amne-
refer to forgetting (English borrows the word ‘amnesia’ from Greek).
Anamnesis adds another negative a-, so it means something like
“un-forgetting” or “de-forgetting,” the opposite of forgetting. So
regathering one’s memories might be thought of as re-collecting,
recollection.
B. In this dialogue, Cebes gives one account of how recollection works
and why learning is recollection, and Socrates gives another. Note that
what Socrates says about how people recollect is not the process he
uses to get Simmias to learn; what Socrates does is more like what
Cebes describes. None of his friends remark on this, but it is
significant: The process Socrates describes does not necessarily
involve reasoning on the part of the learner, but the process Cebes
describes does. The process Socrates uses in his demonstration in fact
involves the kind of questions and reasoning Cebes mentions. And when
Simmias tries to say where his learning came from, he doesn’t mention
reasoning. In fact, Socrates’ friends pay no attention to the role of
reasoning until Socrates draws attention to it from 96-102; and even
then, they would rather hear comforting or exciting ideas than reason
about them. They would rather accept a set of ideas from their teachers
than investigate their fundamental assumptions. They would rather hear
lots of new ideas, and follow lots of paths for short distances than
follow out a line of questions thoroughly.
1.
Specifically, Cebes’ description of the “evidence” that learning is
recollection is that when people are questioned in an appropriate way,
they always give the right answers (even if they did not initially know
the right answers and had not learned the right answers earlier). They
will also be able, if questioned in a certain way, to explain or show
why their answers are correct (73a-b; and as your text notes, Socrates
seems to demonstrate exactly this process of questioning at Meno 81ff.).6
2. Socrates then gives an alternate
version of the “evidence” that learning is recollection, a version he
does not give elsewhere: He says that when one senses or thinks of one
thing, one may be reminded of another quite different thing, and this
is also “recollecting” the second thing (73c-d; note that there is no
mention of questioning here, and no mention of a “right” answer or an
explanation).
C. Socrates now tries to show Simmias that learning is recollection of
things one does not directly sense, and manages to get Simmias to
conclude that the knowledge one recollects must have been acquired by
the soul when the soul was not in a body:
Socrates returns to the idea that philosophers seek knowledge about
things such as “the beautiful itself” (that which all beautiful things
have in common that makes them beautiful), “the just itself” (that
which all just things have in common that makes them just), “the equal
itself” (that which all equal things, or equal pairs or groups, have in
common that makes them equal: equalness, or equality) – 74a, 75c, etc.
(and compare the idea of the pious itself, Euthyphro 5d, 6e).
These are not perceived through the five senses – not only does one not
see or hear justice, for example, but one does not see equality with
one’s eyes. One sees objects and if one has the notion of
equality, one can measure the objects to see whether they are equal.
One can even determine that two things are of equal width if they look
to be of different widths. But children who have not learned the idea
of equality can see the same objects we do and not grasp that they are
equal.
How, then, do we come to grasp what it is to be equal, what makes
things equal, “the equal itself”? Socrates suggests that seeing objects
that are roughly equal “reminds” us of the equal itself, just as seeing
a picture of Simmias “reminds” us of Simmias, or of Cebes (Simmias’
close friend), 74c-d. In fact, the reminding or recollecting process,
as Socrates portrays it to Simmias, is quite involuntary on our part.
The roughly equal objects that we sense “strive” toward the equal
itself (75b) and our sense perceptions of these objects “make” us
realize that the objects are striving toward the equal itself (also
75b).
Let us note that this view of learning seems to conflict with the
account given at 66-69. In that earlier passage, Socrates had proposed,
and Simmias agreed, that the body and senses are nothing but a
hindrance in the search for knowledge. The had portrayed body and
senses as an obstacle that is never helpful. But here, at 73-77, they
say that the senses help one learn, and are not always a hindrance. In
fact, at 73-77, the senses are a necessary tool in the learning process.
Let us also note that the soul seems passive in the account Socrates
and Simmias give at 73-77; it isn’t asking questions or doing any
research or reasoning. It’s just reacting to sense perceptions of
objects that are striving toward some ideal. (How inanimate objects
such as sticks can “strive” is never discussed.)
With this picture in place, a picture of a largely passive soul that is
occasionally reminded of things, Socrates asks when the soul could have
initially gained the knowledge of the equal itself, the just itself,
etc. (the knowledge that it is reminded of in recollection). Simmias
agrees that it did not obtain this knowledge during bodily life, as we
needed to have it in place before all sense perceptions began, and we
have no experience of ourselves or anyone else gaining it by sense
perception during bodily life (75d-e, 76c). Therefore, Simmias says, we
must have acquired this knowledge before birth into a body, and then
forgotten it upon being born into a body (76c-d). (Presumably, all
humans have this ability to recollect, so the recollectable knowledge
must be in our souls prior to our first human incarnation at least.)
Note that Socrates and Simmias have overlooked some possibilities as to
when we could have gained knowledge of the equal itself, the good
itself, etc.:
- we might not now have knowledge of
this kind at all, but only have an approximation developed by
reasoning, imagining, hypothesizing, and experimentation;
- knowledge of this kind may not exist,
so what we have is some sort of generalizations and rules of thumb that
are useful, and which we developed by reasoning, guesswork, trial and
error;
- if we do have knowledge of this kind,
we could have developed it by reasoning, imagining, hypothesizing, and
experimentation.
I suggest that Plato is showing us Simmias’ lack of training in
reasoning, and his ignorance of its role, its proper use, and its
limitations.
There is another problem here: Socrates refers repeatedly to the soul’s
“acquiring” knowledge or “learning” while separated from a body
(75d-76d). But how does it learn while separated? It can’t be by
recollection; that requires a body. And why does the soul need to
acquire knowledge in order to have it – why does Socrates not say that
the knowledge is “built in”? In fact, the notion that it must acquire
knowledge sets up the possibility that it might only get knowledge
after a few incarnations, so that there would be people who would not
be able to recollect correctly because their souls did not have the
right knowledge. This possibility is ignored in the dialogue.
Socrates tries to sum up the argument at 76d-77a by saying that if the
beautiful itself, the good itself, the just itself etc. exist, then our
soul must exist before birth (otherwise we would not be able to compare
sensed things to them); that the beautiful itself etc. and souls that
exist before association with bodies have “equal necessity” of existing
(this doesn’t really follow). This draws our attention to the fact that
no one in the dialogue has attempted to establish that the beautiful
itself, the good itself, etc. really do exist.
But that’s no problem for Simmias. He just assumes that the beautiful
itself, etc. do exist; “Nothing is so evident to me personally” (77a).
And from that he is happy to conclude that the soul exists in between
its associations with bodies.
D. At 77b, both Simmias and Cebes note that this is not enough to
establish that a soul will survive more than a few associations with
bodies, so that perhaps Socrates’ soul has gone through several bodies
but will disintegrate after leaving its current body.
Simmias and Cebes ask Socrates to show them that his soul will survive,
so that they can feel comforted and not fear death (their own or
Socrates’). This is significant because it is one of several reminders
that Simmias and Cebes want to hear arguments that will make them feel
better. One thing the dialogue prompts one to consider, then, is
whether there are other goals for philosophical argument, whether some
of these goals might at times conflict with the goal of feeling
reassured, whether and when being reassured is a suitable goal, and so
on.
Questions, comments?
Contact me at rcherubi(at)gmu(dot)edu.