a. What does
Socrates mean by 'the just itself'? One way to understand this would be
to say that if there are just things, then the just itself is what all
the just things have that
makes
them just. If we say that there can be people who are just, laws that
are just, institutions that are just, and so on, then is there
something that all these things and people have in common that makes
them all merit being called 'just'? Socrates and his friends propose
that there is something that all just things have in common that makes
them just, and that this something is called 'the just itself.'
b. Why, though, does he call this 'the just
itself'? Consider that each if there are things that are just, each of
them has aspects that are not justice: a just person is an animal, a
male or a female; he or she has a certain age, height, and weight; etc.
A just law may deal with one issue or another; it was passed at a
certain date; etc. So 'the just itself' will be part of what the just
human and the just law share, not what they do not share. Also, no one
is perfect; we will still call a person "just" if he or she fails once
or twice to do what is just, but overall tries and succeeds in being
just in the vast majority of cases. Even the laws may not be perfect; a
law might be just in most circumstances, but because of some special
situation may not be just in a particular instance. 'The just itself'
is a notion that helps us identify these deviations: they are the
situations where the person or law fails to exhibit or "participate in"
the just itself.
c. What then does 'participate in' mean? The
Greek word is
metechein,
which means 'to take part in' or 'to partake of.' Part of the idea
seems to be that the just itself is manifested in the things that
"participate in" it.
d. One might object at the outset that
Socrates and his friends have not yet identified who and what is really
just and why these people and things are to be considered just; they
have not yet discovered what justice is. But this objection does not
hold; in fact, the search for "the just itself" is their way of seeking
what justice really is. By examining all the things that
seem just, one can discover whether
patterns emerge. One can also discover contradictions or incoherences
in one's ideas about what qualities exemplify the just thing or person,
and weed those out. By doing this, one can get to the hear of what one
means by 'justice,' see what it is that all things called just might
have in common that makes them just, and see whether these ideas make
sense and truly represent feature of life worth having.
e. Socrates seems to use the phrases 'the just
itself' and 'the form of the just' interchangeably. For more on
'forms,' click
here.
f. One might object that we do not know that
all just things actually have something in common that makes them just.
One would then have to ask, however, why we refer to all of these
things using the same word ('just') if they have nothing in common that
makes them just. If the use of the term 'just' is arbitrary,
capricious, or a matter of fad, then why bother having a justice system
at all? Moreover, the fact that we do not know that all just things do
NOT have something in common that makes them just suggests that the
question deserves further investigation.
More on this
(same link as in part (e) above).
4. The characters agree that it would be
all right if one could not prove that the just-
polis-in-
logos (theory/speech) could really
exist. They also agree that
praxis
(practice) grasps truth less well than
lexis (speaking) does, 473a.
Interestingly, they reach this conclusion through an analogy to
painting: excellence in painting a beautiful person in a picture does
not imply or call for proof that such a beautiful person exists. The
word 'beautiful' translates
kalos,
and
kalos can also mean
'noble, high-minded.'
5. This leads to a discussion of what it is that philosophers love,
namely the whole of wisdom and truth (475b) and the sight of truth
(475e, where 'sight' refers to 'insight' or 'seeing with the mind's
eye' rather than to physical vision). Socrates proposes that the things
that knowledge (as opposed to opinion) is "set over" (i.e. the things
that knowledge refers to or is knowledge "of" - 479e-480a) are "the
things themselves": the beautiful/noble itself, the just itself, the
good itself, etc. These "things themselves" are things that always
remain the same (484c, 485b): the just itself does not ever cease to be
the way it is; it is some stable underlying feature of the universe
that makes just things just.
In contrast, the particular things that
are said to be just might appear to be just in one way and not in
another, or might change from being just to being unjust (a person who
had been just might commit an unjust act for one reason or another, or
might even cease acting just altogether, for example). Thus the
apparently just things exhibit "being" as well as "not being," for they
are just in one way or at one time and are not just in another way or
at another time. According to Socrates, this implies that what is "set
over" these things is opinion, which is intermediate between knowledge
and ignorance. The idea seems to be that knowledge enables one to state
what really is, and ignorance brings one to say that things are not the
way they really are, or to state what "is not" - for example, if you
were ignorant of geography you might say that Nigeria was in Asia, but
that would be stating what is not: Nigeria
is not in Asia, but rather
is in Africa. (Or you might say that Nigeria was in Africa, but it
would be a lucky guess, and you would not know that you were stating
what really is.) Opinion is in between knowledge and ignorance, in that
with opinion you state things that may be part of the truth, but not
the whole truth; you identify aspects of what really is, but not the
whole of it; and by stating just some aspects of what really is, you
distort it and say something of what is not. Also, opinion is not as
well-grounded as knowledge, so in having opinion you do not have the
full grasp of what is. Thus having an opinion about what is just means
having partial awareness of how things are, but not having a full
understanding - and perhaps missing something crucial.
According to Socrates, philosophers
"embrace the thing itself," 480a, which seems to imply that they have
some knowledge. Perhaps it would be more judicious to say that
philosophers seek to embrace the thing itself?
Why is a discussion of the nature of
knowledge in the Republic at
all?
1. In their
discussion of the knowledge philosophers have or seek, the characters
have focused so far on knowledge of beauty/nobility, justice,
moderation, and the like (501b). That is, the knowledge that the
characters have been considering so far is knowledge of moral and
aesthetic matters. One might think then that this is knowledge of what
ought to be, but it has also been described as knowledge of what is,
for the beautiful/noble itself, the just itself, etc. have been
described as "real being" and "things themselves that never change."
Somehow, then, this part of what is also (according to Socrates'
proposals) tells us what ought to be, or describes a direction for our
efforts. The guardians, Socrates says, must know what is good in order
to guard it (506a).
2. In Book VI Socrates presents the famous analogy between the good
itself and the sun - the good itself (that which all good things have
in common that makes them good) is to the realm of understanding as the
sun is to the visible realm; the sun causes sight and makes visible
things visible (or seen), and the good causes understanding (
noesis) and makes understandable
things understandable (or understood), 508-509. That is, things are
illuminated by truth, Socrates says, and what gives truth to the things
known and the power to know to the knower is the good. Socrates goes on
to suggest that the sun may be in some way a cause of seasons, life,
etc. (509c); one might ask whether the influence of good has a
comparable extension.
a. These
points are never explained, and the question of whether the good is
really like the sun in this way is not explored. Therefore it is
important to look at the assumptions underlying the analogy between sun
and good. The account Socrates gives ties all knowledge to good, makes
all knowledge reflect good. This means not merely that knowledge is a
good thing, but also that all known things are known as what they are
known as (and known at all) because of good. What does this mean?
Consider that all colored things have the color they do partly because
of the light source under which they are viewed. That is, a yellow
thing and a white thing look different under white light, but the same
under yellow light. If we follow Socrates' analogy, the good will
"color" or give some form and content to our knowledge. This suggests that all of the
knowledge that the philosopher will seek will be relevant toward
choosing what is best. Even knowledge of things that don't seem
immediately related to the question of what is best might in fact be
relevant.
But this does not yet explain the reasoning behind the claim that the
good informs or makes all knowledge. Is it that
(1) There must be something purposive
or directive or goal-like to the cosmos, because otherwise all attempts
to find direction and appropriate goals will have to rely on something
arbitrary or random (such as whim or prejudice)?
Or is it that
(2) We identify things in a way that reflects our priorities? For
example, we may make a distinction between frogs and toads or not,
depending on what we are interested in doing with regard to these
animals. If we are studying biology, we will make the distinction; if
we are simply watching them hop around while we wait for a bus, we may
not. If the way we identify things reflects our priorities, it will
reflect our beliefs, desires, and opinions.
Now, if we are going to be able to tell
what the things we identify really are so as to have knowledge of them
(or if we are to tell whether what we say is is what is), we need to go
beyond our beliefs, desires, and opinions. our beliefs may be incorrect
or unfounded, our desires might be unrealistic or might blind us ti
some aspects of what is, our opinions might reflect prejudices or
presuppositions. Today in science we tend to think that this means
putting aside desires and so on, but in fact certain unquestioned
purposes, utilities, and suppositions remain to direct or form our
scientific inquiry.
So here we might say: the divisions and
categories we had made for purposes of inquiry or everyday life
reflected our priorities. If we are to come to have knowledge of the
things we identify, we must scrutinize the criteria we used for
identifying things. Without some purpose we would not make
identifications at all, so in order to find the true way things are and
the truthful way of identifying what is we must find what is really
good. That is, if our purposes do not reflect what is truly good, and
if the good itself is present in the universe in a way that orders the
universe, then we will fail to understand what really is. Only if we
can align our purposes and priorities with the good itself will we be
able to tell how things really are. (At least, this is what Socrates'
claims suggest; I am neither endorsing nor condemning them here.)
This assumes, of course, that some way(s) of
identifying things is/are right, and that there is a real way that
things are. It also assumes that through words we can identify the real
natures of things. If these assumptions seem odd (and they are not
argued for), consider these issues: If justice is to be expressed in
law, and if standards of justice are to be communicated, words had
better be able to convey what is real and true. Moreover, if there is
no "good itself," then our notions of good and of justice are just
feelings or beliefs or prejudices, our ways of identifying things are
arbitrary, and there is no way of holding any standard of good or
justice. Feelings change, and we cannot know that we share one
another's feelings; beliefs change; prejudices are capricious and
unfounded. Thus if we develop notions of good and of justice that are
based on feelings, beliefs, and prejudices, and we try to enforce
obedience to these notions in a society, we are fostering tyranny and
opposing justice. If we decide that there are to be no standards, we
have anarchy and no way of holding the society together except by
force - which is what one forms a society in order to escape. Thus
Socrates implies that knowledge, and before it the search for
knowledge, are the only alternatives to this choice between tyranny and
anarchy.
The
Republic as a whole, in
exploring what happens when people who do not yet know what justice is
try to develop a political framework based on what seems good to them
now, shows the necessity of a different kind of search for knowledge.
It also helps us to begin that search - not by doing what the
characters do, but by interrogating their choices and the beliefs we
have concerning the matters of which they speak.
Back to
PHIL 323/GOVT 323 Supplementary Readings page
PHIL
323/GOVT 323 main page
Prof.
Cherubin's main ancient philosophy page