Aristotle now discusses what virtue or excellence must be. In Book One,
Ch. 13, he had said that people distinguish 2 kinds of virtue or
excellence: "intellectual" virtues such as theoretical wisdom (wisdom
involving knowledge of theories, among other things, as described in the Metaphysics),
understanding, and practical wisdom (discussed below); and "moral" or
"ethical" virtues or excellences, such as courage, generosity,
self-control/moderation, and justice. The "moral" virtues are the subject
of the Nicomachean Ethics, and as Aristotle notes, the name
'ethics' in Greek reflects the fact that virtues seem to be developed by
means of habit (ethos in Greek). That is, virtues are not inborn,
to Aristotle, though the capacity to develop virtues is inborn in all of
us. And of course, it is not all habits that impart virtues; there are
also habits that work against virtues. For example, if we develop the
habit of paying no attention to money or to other people's needs, we are
unlikely to become generous (at least, not consistently generous); if we
develop the habit of never trying anything new or unknown, we will not
learn certain kinds of courage.
Chapter 4
Aristotle suggests that we become virtuous by performing virtuous acts,
or by acting virtuous. But he is aware of how odd that sounds. He
clarifies the contention by saying that he does not mean that merely
happening to perform any action that happens to be just makes you just,
that merely happening to do something courageous (or something courageous
people do) means that you are courageous, etc. First of all, some
awareness and skill are involved. We don't say that a person is literate
if he or she can copy letters that someone else wrote, while not knowing
how to read him- or herself. Similarly, we don't say that a person is just
if he or she did something just without knowing that it was just, or
without knowing why it was just - or if he or she only did it because
someone else told him/her what to do, or forced him/her to do it.
Moreover, says Aristotle, "an act is not performed justly or with self-control [simply] if the act is of a certain kind, but only if in addition the agent [(person who does the act)] has certain characteristics as he/she performs it" (1105a). That is, being morally virtuous or excellent requires more than simply doing the right thing. You also have to do it in a certain way, for certain reasons, in order to have true excellence:
- you must know what you are doing (you're not being generous if you don't know the value of what you give, for example)
- you must choose to act the way you do (as opposed to being forced to do something, or doing something by accident)
- you must choose to act this way or to do this thing for its own sake (you're not being courageous if you are acting only to impress people, and would not do the same thing if no one was watching. You must choose your action because you think that it is good in itself.)
- your act must "spring from a firm and unchangeable character or
habit" (you have not acted with moral excellence if you acted on a
whim, or if you simply did what your friends were doing without
considering whether this was an appropriate thing to do - and why. You
must try to be consistent, and if that turns out badly, you must try to
understand why.) (1105a-b)
Chapter 6
Aristotle now tries to determine what virtue or excellence (arete)
involves. He concludes that "virtue or excellence is a characteristic
involving choice; it consists in observing the mean [(middle point)]
relative to us, a mean which is determined by reason, such as a person
of practical wisdom would [use to] determine it." (1107a)
For example, Aristotle will say in Chapter 7, we consider what we call
"courage" to be a virtue (a good quality to have), and it is a mean or
middle point between cowardice and recklessness. We consider what we call
"moderation" or "self-control" to be a virtue, and it is a mean between
insensitivity (lack of feeling or desire; or refusal of all feeling or
desire) and indulgence. In other words, a person is thought to be cowardly
if he/she runs away or surrenders at the slightest sign of threat or
danger, or if he/she exhibits a lot of fear at situations that are not
really very dangerous (or, not considered dangerous by his/her society's
standards) - and acts on that fear. A person is considered to be reckless
if he/she does dangerous things unnecessarily, or shows no fear at things
that are considered (in his/her society) to be very dangerous, etc. The
person who is considered courageous is one who exhibits a level of fear
that is considered (in his/her society) to be appropriate in each
situation, who faces necessary dangers without letting fear get the better
of him/her (this is not the same as not feeling fear at all), and who does
not do dangerous things that are not necessary.
This raises two issues that must be discussed.
Practical wisdom is discussed in Book Six, Chapter 5. There Aristotle
says that practical wisdom is a "truthful characteristic of acting
rationally (literally, 'along with reason') in matters good and bad for
humans." That is, it involves being aware of and preserving (not
denying or ignoring) what is true, and choosing and acting on this in a
reasoning way. The person with practical wisdom (if such a person exists)
will be one who can see what is good for him- or herself and for humans in
general. Practical wisdom, then, includes both an aspect of understanding
and an aspect of action. One who claims to know what to do in a given
situation but then does not act on this will not have practical wisdom.
Aristotle's point concerning virtue or excellence would be that virtue or
excellence involves choosing and doing something appropriate (neither
excessive or deficient) in each situation where choice is involved. But he
emphasizes that some people will not be good judges of this, at least at
first. They may not recognize when choice is really possible, or may not
realize what choices they have. They may be mistaken about what is really
appropriate in each situation. Only the person who has practical wisdom
will know what is right, and will be able to explain why that is what is
right.
This does not mean that we must wait around for someone who convinces us
that he/she has practical wisdom to tell us what to do - for if we lack
practical wisdom, we might not be able to tell who really has it. At the
same time, Aristotle is cautioning us against assuming that we already
know what is right. Instead, he seems to be suggesting that the search for
and development of practical wisdom is an ongoing process, and that it is
important for each one of us to start the process now. That is, we must
start by doing what we think is the "mean" in each situation that involves
a choice. We may start by trying to live up to our society's standards, in
so far as we recognize them. But that is not enough, because we must come
to understand whether these things are really the best to do, whether they
really have the best effects, why they should be chosen, what makes a
particular result the one most worth seeking, and so on. We must observe
and investigate both the actions we perform and the standards we used in
choosing them; and we must evaluate the actions, their results, and our
standards. (This may mean searching for a clear standard, as Socrates
did...) Only if we can show that we understand why an action or its reason
is best, will we really be able to be virtuous or excellent. In the
meantime, the best thing will be to start the investigation of this
(recall Socrates at Apology 38a) - that is, the best thing will be
to search for virtue and practical wisdom. This will require both action
and contemplation or reasoned investigation.
Notes on
Nicomachean Ethics Book II by Rose Cherubin is licensed under a Creative
Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International
License.